您的当前位置:首页正文

Proceedings of the LFG01 Conference

2021-02-04 来源:步旅网
WEAKCROSSOVERANDTHEABSENCEOFTRACESMaryDalrymple,RonaldM.Kaplan,andTracyHollowayKing

XeroxPARCProceedingsoftheLFG01ConferenceUniversityofHongKong,HongKongMiriamButtandTracyHollowayKing(Editors)

2001

CSLIPublications

http://csli-publications.stanford.edu/

Abstract

Weprovideanewdefinitionofthelinearprominenceconstraintsbetweenpronounsandoperators(wh-wordsandquantifiers)whichcorrectlyrulesoutexamplesthatviolateweakcrossover.Previousanalysesofweakcrossoverreliedonthepresenceofatraceintheextractionsiteofawh-question;incontrast,ouranalysisenablesatracelessaccountofexamplespreviouslycitedinsupportoftraces.Sincenootherincontrovertibleevidencefortraceshasbeenputforward,ouraccountallowsare-turntothetracelessandthereforemoreconstrainedaccountoflong-distancebind-inginLFGproposedbyKaplanandZaenen(1989).1

Long-distancedependenciesinLFG

Traceswereintroducedintransformationalgrammar(Chomsky,1973)inordertogiveaphrasalaccountforawiderangeoflong-distancedependencyphenomena:along-distancedependencybetweenadisplacedelementinawh-questionorrel-ativeclausewasassumedtoarisebymovementofthedisplacedelement,whichleavesbehinda‘trace’initsoriginalposition.TheoriginalLFGtreatmentoflongdistancedependencies(KaplanandBresnan,1982)wasbasedonanadaptationofthetransformational/phrase-structurescheme.Therelationbetweenthedisplacedwh-phraseanditswithin-clausefunctionwasdefinedintermsofarelationbetweenthewh-wordandanemptyc-structureconstituent,atrace,withintheclause.Inexample(1),therelationbetweentheNPnodedominatingwhoandtheNPnodedominatingitstrace,representedby,ensuresthatthewh-phrasewhoisboththeFOCUSandtheOBJofthesentence:

(1)

NPCP

CPRED‘greetSUBJ,OBJ’WhoCIPFOCUSPRED‘who’didNPISUBJPRED‘Bill’BillVVPNPOBJtgreetSubsequently,however,KaplanandZaenen(1989)proposedthatconstraintsonlongdistancedependenciesarebeststatedinfunctionalandnotphrasalterms.Assuch,functionaluncertaintyoffersamoreaccurateanddirectcharacterizationof

thelongdistancedependency.Aruleliketheoneinexample(2)establishestworolesfortheNPdaughterofCP:itistheFOCUS,anditplaysagrammaticalroledefinedbythefunctionaluncertaintypathCOMPOBJ:

(2)CP

NP(FOCUS)=(COMP*OBJ)=

C=

Inexample(3),thepathconsistingsimplyofOBJischosen,andtheFOCUSf-structurealsoappearsastheOBJofgreet:(3)WhodidBillgreet?

PRED‘greetSUBJ,OBJ’

FOCUS

PRED‘who’

SUBJ

PRED‘Bill’

OBJ

Withthisaccount,longdistancedependenciesnolongerprovideargumentsthattrace-likedevicesarenecessaryinthetheoryofgrammar.Andinfact,atracelesstheoryispreferredfortworeasons:itismoreadequatedescriptively,anditofferstheoreticaladvantages.Weoutlinethesereasonsbelowbeforediscussingexamplesinvolvingweakcrossoverandhowatracelesstheorycanaccountforthem.

Atracelesstheoryisdescriptivelymoreadequate.Thatis,itcandescribedatathatthetracefultheorycannot,asarguedindetailbyKaplanandZaenen(1989).KaplanandZaenen(1989)citeevidencefromwanderingadverbsinIcelandic,cross-categorialdependenciesinEnglish,andcross-conjunctrelativizationconstraintsinJapanesethatcanbeaccountedfornaturallyinatraceless,butnotatraceful,anal-ysis.Morerecently,Sag(1998)hasprovidedadditionalevidenceagainsttracesinhisanalysisoftheconjunctconstraintandoffloatingquantifiersandadverbs.

Forseveralreasons,atracelesstheoryisalsotheoreticallypreferred.Thatis,evenifthetracelessandtracefultheoriesaccountedforexactlythesamedata,thetracelesstheoryispreferable.First,thetracelesstheoryislessredundantinthatthereisonlyasinglewayofdealingwithlongdistancedependencies;itisagen-eralscientificprinciplethatlessredundanttheoriesarepreferredtomoreredundantones.Second,itismorerestrictiveinthatithasfewerpowerfulmechanismsandismoretractablemathematically.Third,itavoidsspuriouslyambiguousanalysesforfillerswithout‘canonical’phrase-structurepositions.Forexample,inextrac-tionofobliquesandadverbsthereismorethanonepossibleextractionsite,evenin

arelativelyfixedwordorderlanguagelikeEnglish,asshownin(4).(4)a.Obliqueextr.:AboutwhatdidJohntalk

toMary

?

b.Adverbextr.:HowoftendidJohntalk

toMaryaboutapples?

Finally,withthetracelesstheory,thelistener’sperceptualproblemissimpler:thelistenermustguessonlythefunctionofthedisplacedelement,notbothafunctionandaposition.Thus,therearebothempiricalandtheoreticalreasonstopreferthetracelessaccount.2

Weakcrossover:Acounterexample?

Despitetheappealofatracelessanalysisoflongdistancedependencies,thereisevidencethatseemstosuggestthattracescannotbeeliminated:weakcrossover(Postal,1971;Wasow,1979)seemstoindicatethatthelinearpositionencodedbyatracedoesaffectgrammaticality.Thesentencein(5)exemplifiesaweakcrossoverviolation:

(5)*Whodidhismothergreet?

(cannotmean:Whosemothergreetedhim?)

Thename‘crossover’comesfromthetransformationalanalysisofwh-questionfor-mation:inacrossoverviolation,thewh-phrase‘crossesover’acoreferentialpro-nounwhenitismovedtothebeginningofasentence.Inlateranalyses,theviolationhasbeenreformulatedintermsofthepositionofthetrace:acrossoverviolationensueswhen,asin(5),acoreferentialpronounprecedesthetrace.Weconcentratehereonweakcrossoverviolations,thoseinwhichthepronounprecedesbutdoesnotc-commandthetrace.

Crossovereffectsarefoundinoperatorbinding,inparticular,bindingbyWH-operatorsandquantifiers(Reinhart,1983):(6)a.*Whodidhismothergreet?

b.*Hismothergreetedeveryone.

Ourmainfocushereisonthequestionofthenecessityoftraces,andourdiscussionwillcenteraroundoperatorbindinginwh-questions.Wemakeonlysomebriefre-marksbelowaboutquantifierbindinginGerman.

SomerecentLFGaccountsofoperatorbindingandweakcrossoverproposeareturntoatheoryoflongdistancedependencywithtraces(Bresnan,1994,2001;

Berman,2000);thesetheoriesadopttheviewthattherelationbetweenthepronounandatraceofthedisplacedwh-phraseistheimportantoneforcharacterizingweakcrossoverviolations.Thesetheoriesproposearepresentationliketheoneinex-ample(7)foraquestionlikeWhodidhismothergreet?,andruleoutcoreferencebetweenthepronounhisandtheoperatorwhobyreferencetotherelationbetweenthepositionofthepronounandthepositionofthetraceofwho:(7)

NPCP

CPRED‘greetSUBJ,OBJ’WhoCIPFOCUSPRED‘who’didDetNPNISUBJSPECPRED‘pro’VPVNPPRED‘mother’hismotherOBJgreettInthefollowing,weprovideareformulationoftheconstraintsontherelationbe-tweenapronounandanoperatorthatallowanaccountoftheseexampleswithouttraces.3

Prominence

Bresnan(1994,1995,2001)proposesthatoperatorbindingrelationsareconstrainedby(atleast)twodimensionsofprominence:syntacticprominencedependsonthefunctionalrankoftheoperatorandthepronounitbinds,andlinearprominencede-pendsonthelinearorderbetweenanoperatorandapronounthatitbinds.WefirstdiscussBresnan’sdefinitionsandthenprovidearevisedsetofdefinitionsofthesetwoprominencedimensions.3.1

Syntacticandlinearprominence

Bresnan(2001)definesoperatorbindingrequirementsinthefollowingway:

(8)SyntacticProminence(Aunitcontaining)thepronounmaynotbehigher

than(aunitcontaining)theoperatoronthegrammaticalfunctionhier-archy:

SUBJOBJCOMP...

LinearProminenceThepronounmustnotf-precedetheoperator.Bresnanfurtherproposesthatlanguagescanvaryinwhichoftheseconstraintsap-ply:somelanguagesimposebothkindsofprominenceconstraints,somerequireonlyoneortheother,somerequireadisjunctionofthetwo.

WebelievethatBresnan’sbasicinsightiscorrect:prominencerequirementsbe-tweenanoperatorandapronounaremultifaceted,anddifferentlanguagescanim-posedifferentkindsofprominencerequirementsbetweenanoperatorandthepro-nounitbinds.Itturnsout,however,thatasimpleredefinitionofthelinearpromi-nenceconditionmakesmanyofthesamepredictionsasthedefinitionsabove,in-cludingforthecrucialcasesofweakcrossover,withoutassumingtraces.3.2

Rethinkinglinearprominence

Theintuitionbehindourreformulationisthatlinearprecedencerequirementsbe-tweenanoperatorandapronounaredeterminedbytheovertmaterialwhichindi-catesthesyntacticroleofthedisplacedphrase.ThisintuitionfollowstheproposalofSag(1998),thoughitdiffersindetail.

Atheorywithtracesaccountsfortheunacceptabilityofanexamplelike*WhodidSuetalkabouthismotherto?byreferencetotherelationbetweenthepronounhisandthetraceintheobjectpositionofthepronounto,asin(9a).Incontrast,ourtheory(likeSag’s)referstotherelationbetweenthepositionofthepronounandthepositionofthestrandedprepositionto.Thesameresultsobtain,butwithoutpositingatrace,asin(9b).

(9)a.Traces:*WhodidSuetalkabouthismotherto?

b.Notraces:*WhodidSuetalkabouthismother[to]?Wefirstdefinethenotionofcoargumenttoencompasstheargumentsaswellastheadjunctsofasinglepredicate:(10)Coarguments:

theargumentsandadjunctsofasinglepredicate.

Wealsoassumethedefinitionoff-precedencein(11),thoughourproposedredefini-tionoflinearprecedencedoesnotdependonadoptingthisparticularformulationoff-precedenceasopposedtootherdefinitionsoff-precedencethathavebeenadoptedintheliterature(e.g.Bresnan,1995).(11)F-precedence:

f-precedesifandonlyifallc-structurenodescorrespondingtocedeallnodescorrespondingto.(e.g.Kaplan,1989)

pre-

Wenowpresentourrevisedprominencerequirements:

(12)LetCoargOpandCoargProbecoargumentf-structuressuchthatCoargOp

containsOandCoargProcontainsP.Then:

SyntacticProminenceAnoperatorOismoreprominentthanapronounP

ifandonlyifCoargOpisatleastashighasCoargProonthefunctionalhierarchy.LinearProminenceAnoperatorOismoreprominentthanapronounPif

andonlyifCoargOpf-precedesP.Themostimportantdifferencebetweenourreviseddefinitionsandthosein(8)isthatlinearprominencedependsonthef-precedencepropertiesofCoargOp,anf-structurecontainingtheoperator,notontheoperator.4

Evaluatingtheproposal

Inthissection,weshowhowourreviseddefinitionscanaccountforweakcrossoverphenomenainEnglish,German,andMalayalam,withoutpositingtraces.4.1

English

FollowingBresnan(1995),weassumethatinEnglish,theoperatormustoutrankanypronounitbindsinbothLinearProminenceandSyntacticProminence.Withthis,wecorrectlypredicttheunacceptabilityofexample(13):

(13)*Whodidhismothergreet?

CP

NPCPRED‘greetSUBJ,OBJ’

*WhoCIPOBJCoargOp:PRED‘who’didDetNPNISUBJCoargPro:SPECPRED‘pro’VPVPRED‘mother’hismotherFOCUSgreetToapplyourdefinitionsofprominence,wemustfirstlocatethef-structurecoargu-mentsthatcontaintheoperatorandthepronoun.Weobservethefollowing:

SUBJandOBJofgreetarecoarguments

pronounishis

SUBJofgreetcontainsthepronoun,soitisCoargPro

OBJofgreetcontainstheoperator,soitisCoargOp

Onthisbasis,wecheckwhetherbothLinearProminenceandSyntacticProminencearesatisfied.In(13),theOBJwhof-precedesthepronoun,sinceeveryc-structurenodecorrespondingtotheOBJf-structureprecedesthepronoun;thus,theLinearProminencerequirementissatisfied.However,theSyntacticProminencerequire-mentisviolated,sinceCoargPro(SUBJ)outranksCoargOp(OBJ)onthefunctionalhierarchy.Thisaccountfortheunacceptabilityoftheexample.

Next,weexaminethegrammaticalsentenceWhodidSuetalktoabouthismother?:

(14)WhodidSuetalktoabouthismother?

PRED‘talkSUBJ,OBLto,OBLabout’

FOCUSPRED‘who’CPSUBJPRED‘Sue’NPCOBLtoCoargOp:PRED‘toOBJ’WhoCIPOBJPRED‘aboutOBJ’

didNPIOBLaboutCoargPro:OBJSPECPRED‘pro’

SueVPPPVPPPPPRED‘mother’talkNPDetNtoabouthis

Inthisexample:

mother

OBLtoandOBLaboutoftalkarecoarguments

pronounishis

OBLaboutoftalkcontainsthepronoun,soitisCoargPro

OBLtooftalkcontainstheoperator,soitisCoargOp

Again,wechecktomakesurethatbothLinearProminenceandSyntacticPromi-nencearesatisfied.Thesyntacticprominencerequirementissatisfied:weassumethatallobliquesoccupythesamerankonthefunctionalhierarchy,sothatCoargOp(OBLto)isatleastashighasCoargPro(OBLabout)onthefunctionalhierarchy.TheLinearProminencerequirementisalsomet.TheCoargOpf-structurecorre-spondstothec-structurenodesPPandPdominatingto.CoargOpf-precedesthepronounf-structure,andtheLinearPrecedenceconditionismet.Sincebothre-quirementsaresatisfied,theexampleiscorrectlypredictedtobegrammatical.

Finally,weexaminetheungrammaticalexample*WhodidSuetalkabouthismotherto?:

(15)*WhodidSuetalkabouthismotherto?

PRED‘talkSUBJ,OBLto,OBLabout’

FOCUSPRED‘who’CPSUBJPRED‘Sue’NPCOBLtoCoargOp:PRED‘toOBJ’WhoCIPOBJPRED‘aboutOBJ’

didNPIOBLaboutCoargPro:OBJSPECPRED‘pro’

SueVVPPPPPNPDetNPPRED‘mother’talkPabouttohismother

(15)hasthesamecoargumentsas(14).Again,theSyntacticProminencerequire-mentismet,sincethetwoobliquesoccupythesamerankonthefunctionalhierar-chy.Thec-structurenodescorrespondingtoCoargOparethePPandPdominatingto;thesenodesdonotf-precedethepronoun,theLinearPrecedencerequirementisnotmet,andtheexampleiscorrectlyclassifiedasungrammatical.

Thus,wehaveseenthattracesarenotnecessarytoaccountfortheEnglishweakcrossoverdataoncecoargumentsaretakenintoaccount.4.2

German

FollowingBerman(2000)andBresnan(2001),weassumethatoperatorbindinginGermanrequiresthateithertheLinearProminenceortheSyntacticProminencerequirementmustbemet;unlikeEnglish,meetingasinglerequirementsufficesforgrammaticality.

First,weconsidersomepatternsofquantifierbinding.Bothoftheexamplesin(16)aregrammatical:

(16)...dass[jeder][seineMutter]mag

thateveryone-NOMhismotherlikes

(CoargOp,SUBJ)(CoargPro,OBJ)...dass[seineMutter][jeder]magthathismothereveryone-NOMlikes

(CoargPro,OBJ)(CoargOp,SUBJ)‘...thateveryonelikeshismother’

Inexample(17),thequantifierjeder‘everyone’istheCoargOpSUBJ,andCoargProistheOBJ:

SUBJandOBJofmag‘like’arecoarguments

pronounisseine

OBJofmag‘like’isCoargPro

SUBJofmag‘like’isCoargOp

TheSyntacticProminencerequirementismetinbothexamples,sinceSUBJout-ranksOBJ.Sinceonlyasinglerequirementmustbesatisfied,theLinearPromi-nencerequirementneednothold,andtheSUBJandOBJmayappearineitheror-der.

WhentheLinearProminencerequirementismet,theSyntacticProminencere-quirementneednotbemet.Inexample(17),CoargOpistheOBJjeden‘everyone’,andCoargProistheSUBJseineMutter‘hismother’.ThoughtheSyntacticPromi-nencerequirementisnotmet,theCoargOpf-precedesthepronoun,andtheexampleisgrammatical:

(17)...dass[jeden]seineMuttermag

thateveryone-ACChismotherlikes

(CoargOp)

‘...thathismotherlikeseveryone’

SUBJandOBJofmag‘like’arecoarguments

pronounisseine

SUBJofmag‘like’isCoargPro

OBJofmag‘like’isCoargOp

Inexample(18),whichhasthesamecoargumentstructureof(17),neitherrequire-mentismet,andthesentenceisungrammatical:(18)*...dass[seineMutter][jeden]mag

thathismothereveryone-ACClikes

(CoargPro,SUBJ)(CoargOp,OBJ)

‘...thathismotherlikeseveryone’

Wenowturntoexamplesinvolvinglongdistancedependencies.Inexample(19),CoargProistheSUBJof‘say’,seineMutter‘hismother’.CoargOpistheCOMPof‘say’.SinceSUBJoutranksCOMP,CoargOpisnotmoresyntacticallyprominentthanCoargPro.AndsinceCoargOpdoesnotf-precedethepronoun,thelinearprominencerequirementdoesnotholdeither.Sinceneitherrequirementholds,thesentenceisclassifiedasungrammatical.Notethatthereasonfortheungrammat-icalityofexample(19)isnotthatthereisatraceinthesubordinateclause;instead,thesubordinateclauseitselfistreatedastheimportantconstituentindeterminingprecedencerequirementsbetweentheoperatorandthepronoun.(19)*jeden/wenmeinte[seineMutter],[habesiegetr¨ostet]

everyone/whosaidhismotherhassheconsoled

(CoargPro,SUBJ)(CoargOp,COMP)

‘Everyone,hismothersaidthatsheconsoled./Whodidhismothersaythatsheconsoled?’

SUBJandCOMPofmeinte‘say’arecoarguments

pronounisseine

SUBJofmeinte‘say’isCoargPro

COMPofmeinte‘say’isCoargOp

Inexample(20),weevaluatetheprominenceconditionswithrespecttothecoar-gumentSUBJandOBJofgetr¨ostet‘consoled’:theSUBJseineMutter‘hismother’isCoargPro,andtheOBJisCoargOp.TheSyntacticProminenceconditiondoesnothold,sincetheCoargProSUBJoutrankstheCoargOpOBJ.ButtheLinearPromi-nenceconditionholds,sincetheCoargOpf-precedesthepronoun.Thus,theop-eratorbindingconditionsforGermanaremet,andthesentenceispredictedtobegrammatical:

(20)[jeden/wen]sagtesie,habeseineMuttergetr¨ostet

everyone/whosaidshehashismotherconsoled(CoargOp)

‘Everyone,shesaidthathismotherconsoled./Whodidshesaythathismotherconsoled?’

SUBJandOBJofgetr¨ostet‘consoled’arecoarguments

pronounisseine

SUBJofgetr¨ostet‘consoled’isCoargPro

OBJofgetr¨ostet‘consoled’isCoargOp

Thus,weseethatinGermansimplexandcomplexclauses,thereisnoneedtoposittracestoaccountfortheweakcrossoverdata.4.3

Malayalam

Finally,webrieflyexaminethebehaviorof‘nullpronouns’,phonologicallyunre-alizedpronominalelements.AsshownbyMohanan(1982)andBresnan(2001),onlytheLinearProminenceconditionisrelevantinMalayalam:theCoargOpmustf-precedethepronoun,butnosyntacticprominenceconditionisrelevant.Example(21)isungrammaticalwithanovertpronoun:

¯rookut(21)*innaleawa¯resakaa¯riccastriikal.einn[oo¯.t.iyum]sahaayiccu¯¯¯¯¯

helpedyesterdaytheyscoldedwomantodayeachchild

(CoargOp)

‘Todayeachchildhelpedthewomanwhoscoldedthemyesterday.’

SUBJandOBJofsahaayiccu‘helped’arecoarguments

pronounisawa¯re

OBJofsahaayiccu‘helped’isCoargPro

SUBJofsahaayiccu‘helped’isCoargOp

Inthisexample,CoargOpisthequantifierphraseoo¯rookuttiyum.CoargOpdoes..notf-precedetheovertpronounawa¯re,andsotheLinearProminencerequirementisnotmet.

However,withanullpronoun,thesentenceisgrammatical:

e

¯(22)innalerookutsakaa¯riccastriikal.einn[oo¯.t.iyum]sahaayiccu¯¯¯¯¯

yesterday(they)scoldedwomantodayeachchildhelped

(CoargOp)

‘Todayeachchildhelpedthewomanwhoscoldedthemyesterday.’

Thesamecoargumentinformationholdsfor(22)asfor(21).However,thenullpro-noundoesnotcorrespondtoanyc-structurenodes,andsoaccordingtothedefi-nitionoff-precedencein(11),itvacuouslyf-precedesandisf-precededbyeveryotherf-structure.Inparticular,itvacuouslysatisfiestheLinearProminencecondi-tion.Thisexplainsthedifferencebetweentheovertandnullpronounsinexamples(21)and(22).5

Empiricaldifferencesbetweentraceandtracelessaccounts

ThoughthedatafromEnglish,German,andMalayalamdiscussedaboveareclassi-fiedcorrectlybyourtheoryofprominenceaswellasbytheoriesthatassumetraces,thereareempiricallytestabledifferencesbetweenthetwoapproaches;inparticu-lar,theavailabilityofcertainsetsofdatawouldallowustodistinguishbetweenourtracelessaccountandtheaccountsofBresnan(1994),Bresnan(2001),andBerman(2000),whichassumetraces.Thoughwehavenotyetbeenabletofindthecrucialdatathatwouldallowustodecidebetweenthetwotheories,weprovidecharacter-izationsofsomeofthesedifferencesinthefollowing,inhopesthatsomeofthesecrucialdatacanbefoundandexamined.5.1

Language1

WefirstexaminewhatwewillcallLanguage1,alanguageinwhichtheSyntacticProminenceconditiondoesnotapply.Morespecifically,Language1hasthefol-lowingcharacteristics:

Fixedwordorder

Wh-phrasesaredisplacedtothebeginningofthesentence

OnlyLinearProminenceisrelevant

InLanguage1,ourtheorypredictsthatanexamplelike(23)wouldbegrammatical,sinceCoargOpprecedesthepronoun,andbyhypothesistheSyntacticProminenceconditiondoesnotapply:

(23)[who]did[hismother]see()

(CoargOp,OBJ)(CoargPro,SUBJ)

e

Incontrast,thetracefultheorypredictsungrammaticality,sincethepronounout-ranksthe(traceofthe)operatorinLinearProminence.5.2

Language2

WenextexamineLanguage2,alanguageinwhichtheobjectprecedesthesubject.Language2hasthefollowingcharacteristics:

Fixedwordorder;Objectprecedessubject

Wh-phrasesaredisplacedtothebeginningofthesentence

BothLinearProminenceandSyntacticProminencemusthold

InLanguage2,ourtheorypredictsgrammaticalityforexample(24):sawhisbook()(24)[who]

(CoargOp,SUBJ)(CoargPro,OBJ)

HeretheSyntacticProminencerequirementholds,sinceCoargOpisSUBJandCoargProisOBJ.TheLinearProminencerequirementisalsomet,sinceCoargOpprecedesthepronoun.Incontrast,thetracefultheorypredictsungrammaticality,sincethepronounprecedesthetrace.5.3

Language3

Finally,weexamineLanguage3,alanguageinwhicheitherprominencerequire-mentmusthold.Language3hasthefollowingcharacteristics:

Fixedwordorder;Subjectprecedesobject

Wh-phrasesaredisplacedtothebeginningofthesentence

EitherLinearProminenceorSyntacticProminencemusthold

Ourtheorypredictsgrammaticalityforexample(25):sawitsowner()(25)[what]

(CoargOp,OBJ)(CoargPro,SUBJ)

TheSyntacticProminencerequirementisnotmetinthisexample,sinceCoargOpisOBJandCoargProisSUBJ.However,theLinearProminencerequirementismet,sinceCoargOpprecedesthepronoun.Thetracefultheorypredictsthatthisexampleisungrammatical,however,sinceonceagainthepronounprecedesthetrace.

6Summary

Ourtracelesstheoryofweakcrossoveraccountsforthedataonweakcrossoverthatmotivatedpreviousresearcherstoposittracesinlongdistancedependencies.WeaccomplishedthisbyprovidinganewdefinitionofLinearProminencewhichap-pliestof-structureunitsthatcontaintheoperator.Sinceweareawareofnootherevidencesupportingtheexistenceoftracesinlongdistancedependencies,webe-lievethattracesremainunmotivatedinthetheoryofgrammar.Acknowledgments

WearegratefultoYehudaFalkandtheaudienceatLFG2001forhelpfuldiscussionandcomments.References

Berman,Judith.2000.TopicsintheClausalSyntaxofGerman.Ph.D.thesis,Uni-versityofStuttgart,Stuttgart,Germany.Bresnan,Joan.1994.Linearordervs.syntacticrank:evidencefromweakcrossover.InKatieBeals,JeannetteDenton,BobKnippen,LynetteMelnar,HisamiSuzuki,andErikaZeinfeld(editors),PapersfromtheThirtiethRegionalMeetingoftheChicagoLinguisticSociety.UniversityofChicago:ChicagoLinguisticSociety.Bresnan,Joan.1995.Linearorder,syntacticrank,andemptycategories:Onweakcrossover.InMaryDalrymple,RonaldM.Kaplan,JohnT.Maxwell,andAnnieZaenen(editors),FormalIssuesinLexical-FunctionalGrammar,pp.241–274.StanfordUniversity:CSLIPublications.Bresnan,Joan.2001.Lexical-FunctionalSyntax.Oxford:BlackwellPublishers.Chomsky,Noam.1973.Conditionsontransformations.InStephenAndersonandPaulKiparsky(editors),AFestschriftforMorrisHalle.NewYork:Holt,Rein-hart,andWinston.Dalrymple,Mary,RonaldM.Kaplan,JohnT.Maxwell,III,andAnnieZaenen(edi-tors).1995.FormalIssuesinLexical-FunctionalGrammar.StanfordUniversity:CSLIPublications.Kaplan,RonaldM.1989.TheformalarchitectureofLexical-FunctionalGrammar.InChu-RenHuangandKeh-JiannChen(editors),ProceedingsofROCLINGII,pp.3–18.ReprintedinDalrympleetal.(1995,pp.7–27).

Kaplan,RonaldM.andJoanBresnan.1982.Lexical-FunctionalGrammar:Afor-malsystemforgrammaticalrepresentation.InJoanBresnan(editor),TheMentalRepresentationofGrammaticalRelations,pp.173–281.Cambridge,MA:TheMITPress.ReprintedinDalrympleetal.(1995,pp.29–130).Kaplan,RonaldM.andAnnieZaenen.1989.Long-distancedependencies,con-stituentstructure,andfunctionaluncertainty.InMarkBaltinandAnthonyKroch(editors),AlternativeConceptionsofPhraseStructure,pp.17–42.ChicagoUni-versityPress.ReprintedinDalrympleetal.(1995,pp.137–165).Mohanan,K.P.1982.GrammaticalrelationsandclausestructureinMalayalam.InJoanBresnan(editor),TheMentalRepresentationofGrammaticalRelations,pp.504–589.Cambridge,MA:TheMITPress.Postal,PaulM.1971.Cross-OverPhenomena.NewYork:Holt,Rinehart,andWinston.Reinhart,Tanya.1983.AnaphoraandSemanticInterpretation.Chicago:TheUni-versityofChicagoPress.Sag,IvanA.1998.Withoutatrace.

MS,

StanfordUniversity.

Wasow,Thomas.1979.AnaphorainGenerativeGrammar.Ghent:E.Story.Addresses:

dalrymple,kaplan,thking@parc.xerox.comXeroxPARC,PaloAlto,CA94304USA

因篇幅问题不能全部显示,请点此查看更多更全内容